Two defenses of epistemic impurism
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.15448/1984-6746.2019.3.35108Keywords:
Epistemic Impurism, Epistemology, Inductive Risk, Philosophy of Science.Abstract
One of the basis of the epistemic tradition is the idea that practical interests do not relate with the truth conditions of knowledge ascription sentences. We will call this thesis of purism, and impurism the thesis that practical factors are constitutive of truth conditions of knowledge ascriptions sentences. In the first part we will discuss Heather Douglas’ impurist view, based on the “inductive risk” notion. For that we will
clarify what is inductive risk, arguing how it requires the idea that practical factors influence on epistemic justification. In the second part we will discuss the defense of “pragmatic encroachment” impurist principles, that is: (a) if a subject knows a proposition, then this proposition is able to figure as practical reason for this subject;
(b) knowledge changes with practical factors. At the end of this article we will trace some conclusions about how these two impurist views are related.
Downloads
References
BIDDLE, J. “State of the field: Transient underdetermination and values in science”. In: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. Vol 44. 2013. P. 124-133. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2012.09.003
COHEN, S. “Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons.” In: TOMBERLIN, J. (Ed) Philosophical Perspectives. Cambridge: Blackwell, 1999. p. 57-89. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/0029-4624.33.s13.3
DeROSE, K. “Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 1992. p. 913–929. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2107917
DOUGLAS, H. “Inductive Risk and Values in Science”. In: Philosophy of Science. Vol 67, n. 4, 2000. P. 559-579. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1086/392855
FANTL, J.; McGRATH, M. Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199550623.001.0001
FANTL, J.; “Arguing for Shifty Epistemology” In: BROWN, J.; GERKEN, M. (orgs) Knowledge Ascriptions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012d. p. 55-74. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199693702.003.0003
HEMPEL, C.G. “Science and Human Values”. In: Aspects of Scientific Explanation and other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: The Free Press, 1965. P. 81-96.
NAGEL, J. “Knowledge ascriptions and the Psychological Consequences of Changing Stakes”. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86, 2008, p. 279-294. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/00048400801886397
NAGEL,J. “Epistemic Anxiety and Apadtive Invariantism” Philosophical Perspectives, 24, v.1, 2010, p. 407-435. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1520-8583.2010.00198.x
SCHAEFFER, J. “The Irrelevance of the Subject: Against Subject-Sensitive Invariantism” Philosophical Studies, 127, 2006, p. 87-107. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-005-1731-9
SCHROEDER, M. “Stakes, Withholding and pragmatic encroachment” Philosophical Studies, 160 (2), 2012, p. 265-285 DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9718-1
SRIPADA, C.; STANLEY, J. “Empirical tests of interest-relative invariantism” Episteme, V.9, Issue 01, Março 2012, pp 3 – 26 DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2011.2
STANLEY, J. Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/0199288038.001.0001